|
|
|
|
Dialectical
materialism is the world outlook of the Marxist-Leninist party. It is called
dialectical materialism because its approach to the phenomena of nature, its
method of studying and apprehending them, is dialectical, while its
interpretation of the phenomena of nature, its conception of these phenomena,
its theory, is materialistic.
Historical
materialism is the extension of the principles of dialectical materialism to
the study of social life, an application of the principles of dialectical
materialism to the phenomena of the life of society, to the study of society
and of its history.
When
describing their dialectical method, Marx and Engels usually refer to Hegel as
the philosopher who formulated the main features of dialectics. This, however,
does not mean that the dialectics of Marx and Engels is identical with the
dialectics of Hegel. As a matter of fact, Marx and Engels took from the
Hegelian dialectics only its "rational kernel," casting aside its
Hegelian idealistic shell, and developed dialectics further so as to lend it a
modern scientific form.
"My
dialectic method," says Marx, "is not only different from the
Hegelian, but is its direct opposite. To Hegel, ... the process of thinking
which, under the name of 'the Idea,' he even transforms into an independent
subject, is the demiurgos (creator) of the real world, and the real world is
only the external, phenomenal form of 'the Idea.' With me, on the contrary, the
ideal is nothing else than the material world reflected by the human mind and
translated into forms of thought." (Marx, Afterword to the Second German Edition
of Volume I of Capital.)
When
describing their materialism, Marx and Engels usually refer to Feuerbach as the
philosopher who restored materialism to its rights. This, however, does not
mean that the materialism of Marx and Engels is identical with Feuerbach's
materialism. As a matter of fact, Marx and Engels took from Feuerbach's
materialism its "inner kernel," developed it into a
scientific-philosophical theory of materialism and cast aside its idealistic
and religious-ethical encumbrances. We know that Feuerbach, although he was
fundamentally a materialist, objected to the name materialism. Engels more than
once declared that "in spite of" the materialist
"foundation," Feuerbach "remained... bound by the traditional
idealist fetters," and that "the real idealism of Feuerbach becomes
evident as soon as we come to his philosophy of religion and ethics."
(Marx and Engels, Vol. XIV, pp. 652-54.)
Dialectics
comes from the Greek dialego, to discourse, to debate. In ancient times
dialectics was the art of arriving at the truth by disclosing the
contradictions in the argument of an opponent and overcoming these
contradictions. There were philosophers in ancient times who believed that the
disclosure of contradictions in thought and the clash of opposite opinions was
the best method of arriving at the truth. This dialectical method of thought,
later extended to the phenomena of nature, developed into the dialectical
method of apprehending nature, which regards the phenomena of nature as being
in constant movement and undergoing constant change, and the development of
nature as the result of the development of the contradictions in nature, as the
result of the interaction of opposed forces in nature.
In
its essence, dialectics is the direct opposite of metaphysics.
1)
Marxist Dialectical Method
The
principal features of the Marxist dialectical method are as follows:
a) Nature Connected and
Determined
Contrary
to metaphysics, dialectics does not regard nature as an accidental
agglomeration of things, of phenomena, unconnected with, isolated from, and
independent of, each other, but as a connected and integral whole, in which
things, phenomena are organically connected with, dependent on, and determined
by, each other.
The
dialectical method therefore holds that no phenomenon in nature can be
understood if taken by itself, isolated from surrounding phenomena, inasmuch as
any phenomenon in any realm of nature may become meaningless to us if it is not
considered in connection with the surrounding conditions, but divorced from
them; and that, vice versa, any phenomenon can be understood and explained if
considered in its inseparable connection with surrounding phenomena, as one
conditioned by surrounding phenomena.
b)
Nature is a State of Continuous Motion and Change
Contrary
to metaphysics, dialectics holds that nature is not a state of rest and
immobility, stagnation and immutability, but a state of continuous movement and
change, of continuous renewal and development, where something is always
arising and developing, and something always disintegrating and dying away.
The
dialectical method therefore requires that phenomena should be considered not
only from the standpoint of their interconnection and interdependence, but also
from the standpoint of their movement, their change, their development, their
coming into being and going out of being.
The
dialectical method regards as important primarily not that which at the given
moment seems to be durable and yet is already beginning to die away, but that
which is arising and developing, even though at the given moment it may appear
to be not durable, for the dialectical method considers invincible only that which
is arising and developing.
"All
nature," says Engels, "from the smallest thing to the biggest. from
grains of sand to suns, from protista (the primary living cells – J. St.) to
man, has its existence in eternal coming into being and going out of being, in
a ceaseless flux, in unresting motion and change (Ibid., p. 484.)
Therefore,
dialectics, Engels says, "takes things and their perceptual images
essentially in their interconnection, in their concatenation, in their
movement, in their rise and disappearance." (Marx and Engels, Vol. XIV,'
p. 23.)
c)
Natural Quantitative Change Leads to Qualitative Change
Contrary
to metaphysics, dialectics does not regard the process of development as a
simple process of growth, where quantitative changes do not lead to qualitative
changes, but as a development which passes from insignificant and imperceptible
quantitative changes to open' fundamental changes' to qualitative changes; a
development in which the qualitative changes occur not gradually, but rapidly
and abruptly, taking the form of a leap from one state to another; they occur
not accidentally but as the natural result of an accumulation of imperceptible
and gradual quantitative changes.
The
dialectical method therefore holds that the process of development should be
understood not as movement in a circle, not as a simple repetition of what has
already occurred, but as an onward and upward movement, as a transition from an
old qualitative state to a new qualitative state, as a development from the
simple to the complex, from the lower to the higher:
"Nature,"
says Engels, "is the test of dialectics. and it must be said for modern
natural science that it has furnished extremely rich and daily increasing
materials for this test, and has thus proved that in the last analysis nature's
process is dialectical and not metaphysical, that it does not move in an
eternally uniform and constantly repeated circle. but passes through a real
history. Here prime mention should be made of Darwin, who dealt a severe blow
to the metaphysical conception of nature by proving that the organic world of
today, plants and animals, and consequently man too, is all a product of a
process of development that has been in progress for millions of years."
(Ibid., p. 23.)
Describing
dialectical development as a transition from quantitative changes to qualitative
changes, Engels says:
"In
physics ... every change is a passing of quantity into quality, as a result of
a quantitative change of some form of movement either inherent in a body or
imparted to it. For example, the temperature of water has at first no effect on
its liquid state; but as the temperature of liquid water rises or falls, a
moment arrives when this state of cohesion changes and the water is converted
in one case into steam and in the other into ice.... A definite minimum current
is required to make a platinum wire glow; every metal has its melting
temperature; every liquid has a definite freezing point and boiling point at a
given pressure, as far as we are able with the means at our disposal to attain
the required temperatures; finally, every gas has its critical point at which,
by proper pressure and cooling, it can be converted into a liquid state.... What
are known as the constants of physics (the point at which one state passes into
another – J. St.) are in most cases nothing but designations for the nodal
points at which a quantitative (change) increase or decrease of movement causes
a qualitative change in the state of the given body, and at which,
consequently, quantity is transformed into quality." (Ibid., pp. 527-28.)
Passing to chemistry,
Engels continues:
"Chemistry
may be called the science of the qualitative changes which take place in bodies
as the effect of changes of quantitative composition. his was already known to
Hegel.... Take oxygen: if the molecule contains three atoms instead of the
customary two, we get ozone, a body definitely distinct in odor and reaction
from ordinary oxygen. And what shall we say of the different proportions in
which oxygen combines with nitrogen or sulphur, and each of which produces a
body qualitatively different from all other bodies !" (Ibid., p. 528.)
Finally,
criticizing Dühring, who scolded Hegel for all he was worth, but
surreptitiously borrowed from him the well-known thesis that the transition
from the insentient world to the sentient world, from the kingdom of inorganic
matter to the kingdom of organic life, is a leap to a new state, Engels says:
"This
is precisely the Hegelian nodal line of measure relations in which at certain
definite nodal points, the purely quantitative increase or decrease gives rise
to a qualitative leap, for example, in the case of water which is heated or
cooled, where boiling point and freezing point are the nodes at which – under
normal pressure – the leap to a new aggregate state takes place, and where
consequently quantity is transformed into quality." (Ibid., pp. 45-46.)
d) Contradictions
Inherent in Nature
Contrary
to metaphysics, dialectics holds that internal contradictions are inherent in
all things and phenomena of nature, for they all have their negative and
positive sides, a past and a future, something dying away and something
developing; and that the struggle between these opposites, the struggle between
the old and the new, between that which is dying away and that which is being
born, between that which is disappearing and that which is developing,
constitutes the internal content of the process of development, the internal
content of the transformation of quantitative changes into qualitative changes.
The
dialectical method therefore holds that the process of development from the
lower to the higher takes place not as a harmonious unfolding of phenomena, but
as a disclosure of the contradictions inherent in things and phenomena, as a
"struggle" of opposite tendencies which operate on the basis of these
contradictions.
"In
its proper meaning," Lenin says, "dialectics is the study of the
contradiction within the very essence of things." (Lenin, Philosophical
Notebooks, p. 265.)
And
further:
"Development
is the 'struggle' of opposites." (Lenin, Vol. XIII, p. 301.)
Such,
in brief, are the principal features of the Marxist dialectical method.
It
is easy to understand how immensely important is the extension of the
principles of the dialectical method to the study of social life and the
history of society, and how immensely important is the application of these
principles to the history of society and to the practical activities of the
party of the proletariat.
If
there are no isolated phenomena in the world, if all phenomena are
interconnected and interdependent, then it is clear that every social system
and every social movement in history must be evaluated not from the standpoint
of "eternal justice" or some other preconceived idea, as is not
infrequently done by historians, but from the standpoint of the conditions
which gave rise to that system or that social movement and with which they are
connected.
The
slave system would be senseless, stupid and unnatural under modern conditions.
But under the conditions of a disintegrating primitive communal system, the
slave system is a quite understandable and natural phenomenon, since it
represents an advance on the primitive communal system
The
demand for a bourgeois-democratic republic when tsardom and bourgeois society
existed, as, let us say, in Russia in 1905, was a quite understandable, proper
and revolutionary demand; for at that time a bourgeois republic would have
meant a step forward. But now, under the conditions of the U.S.S.R., the demand
for a bourgeois-democratic republic would be a senseless and
counterrevolutionary demand; for a bourgeois republic would be a retrograde
step compared with the Soviet republic.
Everything depends on the
conditions, time and place.
It
is clear that without such a historical approach to social phenomena, the
existence and development of the science of history is impossible; for only
such an approach saves the science of history from becoming a jumble of
accidents and an agglomeration of most absurd mistakes.
Further,
if the world is in a state of constant movement and development, if the dying
away of the old and the upgrowth of the new is a law of development, then it is
clear that there can be no "immutable" social systems, no
"eternal principles" of private property and exploitation, no
"eternal ideas" of the subjugation of the peasant to the landlord, of
the worker to the capitalist.
Hence,
the capitalist system can be replaced by the socialist system, just as at one
time the feudal system was replaced by the capitalist system.
Hence,
we must not base our orientation on the strata of society which are no longer
developing, even though they at present constitute the predominant force, but
on those strata which are developing and have a future before them, even though
they at present do not constitute the predominant force.
In
the eighties of the past century, in the period of the struggle between the
Marxists and the Narodniks, the proletariat in Russia constituted an
insignificant minority of the population, whereas the individual peasants
constituted the vast majority of the population. But the proletariat was
developing as a class, whereas the peasantry as a class was disintegrating. And
just because the proletariat was developing as a class the Marxists based their
orientation on the proletariat. And they were not mistaken; for, as we know,
the proletariat subsequently grew from an insignificant force into a first-rate
historical and political force.
Hence,
in order not to err in policy, one must look forward, not backward.
Further,
if the passing of slow quantitative changes into rapid and abrupt qualitative
changes is a law of development, then it is clear that revolutions made by oppressed
classes are a quite natural and inevita
Hence,
the transition from capitalism to socialism and the liberation of the working
class from the yoke of capitalism cannot be effected by slow changes, by
reforms, but only by a qualitative change of the capitalist system, by
revolution.
Hence,
in order not to err in policy, one must be a revolutionary, not a reformist.
Further,
if development proceeds by way of the disclosure of internal contradictions, by
way of collisions between opposite forces on the basis of these contradictions
and so as to overcome these contradictions, then it is clear that the class
struggle of the proletariat is a quite natural and inevitable phenomenon.
Hence,
we must not cover up the contradictions of the capitalist system, but disclose
and unravel them; we must not try to check the class struggle but carry it to
its conclusion.
Hence,
in order not to err in policy, one must pursue an uncompromising proletarian
class policy, not a reformist policy of harmony of the interests of the
proletariat and the bourgeoisie, not a compromisers' pol
Such
is the Marxist dialectical method when applied to social life, to the history
of society.
As
to Marxist philosophical materialism, it is fundamentally the direct opposite
of philosophical idealism.
2) Marxist Philosophical
Materialism
The
principal features of Marxist philosophical materialism are as follows:
a) Materialist
Contrary
to idealism, which regards the world as the embodiment of an "absolute
idea," a "universal spirit," "consciousness," Marx's
philosophical materialism holds that the world is by its very nature material,
that the multifold phenomena of the world constitute different forms of matter
in motion, that interconnection and interdependence of phenomena as established
by the dialectical method, are a law of the development of moving matter, and
that the world develops in accordance with the laws of movement of matter and
stands in no need of a "universal spirit."
"The
materialistic outlook on nature," says Engels, "means no more than
simply conceiving nature just as it exists, without any foreign
admixture." (Marx and Engels, Vol. XIV, p. 651.)
Speaking
of the materialist views of the ancient philosopher Heraclitus, who held that
"the world, the all in one, was not created by any god or any man, but
was, is and ever will be a living flame, systematically flaring up and
systematically dying down"' Lenin comments: "A very good exposition
of the rudiments of dialectical materialism." (Lenin, Philosophical
Notebooks, p. 318.)
b) Objective Reality
Contrary
to idealism, which asserts that only our consciousness really exists, and that
the material world, being, nature, exists only in our consciousness' in our
sensations, ideas and perceptions, the Marxist philosophical materialism holds
that matter, nature, being, is an objective reality existing outside and
independent of our consciousness; that matter is primary, since it is the
source of sensations, ideas, consciousness, and that consciousness is
secondary, derivative, since it is a reflection of matter, a reflection of
being; that thought is a product of matter which in its development has reached
a high degree of perfection, namely, of the brain, and the brain is the organ
of thought; and that therefore one cannot separate thought from matter without
committing a grave error. Engels says:
"The
question of the relation of thinking to being, the relation of spirit to nature
is the paramount question of the whole of philosophy.... The answers which the
philosophers gave to this question split them into two great camps. Those who
asserted the primacy of spirit to nature ... comprised the camp of idealism.
The others, who regarded nature as primary, belong to the various schools of
materialism." (Marx, Selected Works, Vol. I, p. 329.)
And
further:
"The
material, sensuously perceptible world to which we ourselves belong is the only
reality.... Our consciousness and thinking, however supra-sensuous they may
seem, are the product of a material, bodily organ, the brain. Matter is not a
product of mind, but mind itself is merely the highest product of matter."
(Ibid., p. 332.)
Concerning
the question of matter and thought, Marx says:
"It
is impossible to separate thought from matter that thinks. Matter is the
subject of all changes." (Ibid., p. 302.)
Describing
Marxist philosophical materialism, Lenin says:
"Materialism
in general recognizes objectively real being (matter) as independent of
consciousness, sensation, experience.... Consciousness is only the reflection
of being, at best an approximately true (adequate, perfectly exact) reflection
of it." (Lenin, Vol. XIII, pp. 266-67.)
And
further:
–
"Matter is that which, acting upon our sense-organs, produces sensation;
matter is the objective reality given to us in sensation.... Matter, nature,
being, the physical-is primary, and spirit, consciousness, sensation, the
psychical-is secondary." (Ibid., pp. 119-20.)
–
"The world picture is a picture of how matter moves and of how 'matter
thinks.'" (Ibid., p. 288.)
–
"The brain is the organ of thought." (Ibid., p. 125.)
c) The World and Its
Laws Are Knowable
Contrary
to idealism, which denies the possibility of knowing the world and its laws,
which does not believe in the authenticity of our knowledge, does not recognize
objective truth, and holds that the world is full of
"things-in-themselves" that can never be known to science, Marxist
philosophical materialism holds that the world and its laws are fully knowable,
that our knowledge of the laws of nature, tested by experiment and practice, is
authentic knowledge having the validity of objective truth, and that there are
no things in the world which are unknowable, but only things which are as yet
not known, but which will be disclosed and made known by the efforts of science
and practice.
Criticizing
the thesis of Kant and other idealists that the world is unknowable and that
there are "things-in-themselves" which are unknowable, and defending
the well-known materialist thesis that our knowledge is authentic knowledge,
Engels writes:
"The
most telling refutation of this as of all other philosophical crotchets is
practice, namely, experiment and industry. If we are able to prove the
correctness of our conception of a natural process by making it ourselves,
bringing it into being out of its conditions and making it serve our own
purposes into the bargain, then there is an end to the Kantian ungraspable
'thing-in-itself.' The chemical substances produced in the bodies of plants and
animals remained such 'things-in-themselves' until organic chemistry began to
produce them one after another, whereupon the 'thing-in-itself' became a thing
for us, as, for instance, alizarin, the coloring matter of the madder, which we
no longer trouble to grow ill the madder roots in the field, but produce much
more cheaply and simply from coal tar. For 300 years the Copernican solar
system was a hypothesis with a hundred, a thousand or ten thousand chances to
one in its favor, but still always a hypothesis. But when Leverrier, by means
of the data provided by this system, not only deduced the necessity of the
existence of an unknown planet, but also calculated the position in the heavens
which this planet must necessarily occupy, and when Galle really found this
planet, the Copernican system was proved." (Marx, Selected Works, Vol. I,
p. 330.)
Accusing
Bogdanov, Bazarov, Yushkevich and the other followers of Mach of fideism (a
reactionary theory, which prefers faith to science) and defending the
well-known materialist thesis that our scientific knowledge of the laws of
nature is authentic knowledge, and that the laws of science represent objective
truth, Lenin says:
"Contemporary
fideism does not at all reject science; all it rejects is the 'exaggerated
claims' of science, to wit, its claim to objective truth. If objective truth
exists (as the materialists think), if natural science, reflecting the outer
world in human 'experience,' is alone capable of giving us objective truth,
then all fideism is absolutely refuted." (Lenin, Vol. XIII, p. 102.)
Such,
in brief, are the characteristic features of the Marxist philosophical
materialism.
It
is easy to understand how immensely important is the extension of the principles
of philosophical materialism to the study of social life, of the history of
society, and how immensely important is the application of these principles to
the history of society and to the practical activities of the party of the
proletariat.
If
the connection between the phenomena of nature and their interdependence are
laws of the development of nature, it follows, too, that the connection and
interdependence of the phenomena of social life are laws of the development of
society, and not something accidental.
Hence,
social life, the history of society, ceases to be an agglomeration of
"accidents", for the history of society becomes a development of
society according to regular laws, and the study of the history of society
becomes a science.
Hence,
the practical activity of the party of the proletariat must not be based on the
good wishes of "outstanding individuals." not on the dictates of
"reason," "universal morals," etc., but on the laws of
development of society and on the study of these laws.
Further,
if the world is knowable and our knowledge of the laws of development of nature
is authentic knowledge, having the validity of objective truth, it follows that
social life, the development of society, is also knowable, and that the data of
science regarding the laws of development of society are authentic data having
the validity of objective truths.
Hence,
the science of the history of society, despite all the complexity of the
phenomena of social life, can become as precise a science as, let us say,
biology, and capable of making use of the laws of development of society for
practical purposes.
Hence,
the party of the proletariat should not guide itself in its practical activity
by casual motives, but by the laws of development of society, and by practical
deductions from these laws.
Hence,
socialism is converted from a dream of a better future for humanity into a
science.
Hence,
the bond between science and practical activity, between theory and practice,
their unity, should be the guiding star of the party of the proletariat.
Further,
if nature, being, the material world, is primary, and consciousness, thought,
is secondary, derivative; if the material world represents objective reality
existing independently of the consciousness of men, while consciousness is a
reflection of this objective reality, it follows that the material life of
society, its being, is also primary, and its spiritual life secondary,
derivative, and that the material life of society is an objective reality
existing independently of the will of men, while the spiritual life of society
is a reflection of this objective reality, a reflection of being.
Hence,
the source of formation of the spiritual life of society, the origin of social
ideas, social theories, political views and political institutions, should not
be sought for in the ideas, theories, views and political institutions
themselves, but in the conditions of the material life of society, in social
being, of which these ideas, theories, views, etc., are the reflection.
Hence,
if in different periods of the history of society different social ideas,
theories, views and political institutions are to be observed; if under the
slave system we encounter certain social ideas, theories, views and political
institutions, under feudalism others, and under capitalism others still, this
is not to be explained by the "nature", the "properties" of
the ideas, theories, views and political institutions themselves but by the
different conditions of the material life of society at different periods of
social development.
Whatever
is the being of a society, whatever are the conditions of material life of a
society, such are the ideas, theories political views and political
institutions of that society.
In
this connection, Marx says:
"It
is not the consciousness of men that determines their being, but, on the
contrary, their social being that determines their consciousness." (Marx Selected
Works, Vol. I, p. 269.)
Hence,
in order not to err in policy, in order not to find itself in the position of
idle dreamers, the party of the proletariat must not base its activities on
abstract "principles of human reason", but on the concrete conditions
of the material life of society, as the determining force of social
development; not on the good wishes of "great men," but on the real
needs of development of the material life of society.
The
fall of the utopians, including the Narodniks, anarchists and
Socialist-Revolutionaries, was due, among other things to the fact that they
did not recognize the primary role which the conditions of the material life of
society play in the development of society, and, sinking to idealism, did not
base their practical activities on the needs of the development of the material
life of society, but, independently of and in spite of these needs, on
"ideal plans" and "all-embracing projects", divorced from
the real life of society.
The
strength and vitality of Marxism-Leninism lies in the fact that it does base
its practical activity on the needs of the development of the material life of
society and never divorces itself from the real life of society.
It
does not follow from Marx's words, however, that social ideas, theories,
political views and political institutions are of no significance in the life
of society, that they do not reciprocally affect social being, the development
of the material conditions of the life of society. We have been speaking so far
of the origin of social ideas, theories, views and political institutions, of
the way they arise, of the fact that the spiritual life of society is a
reflection of the conditions of its material life. As regards the significance
of social ideas, theories, views and political institutions, as regards their
role in history, historical materialism, far from denying them, stresses the
important role and significance of these factors in the life of society, in its
history.
There
are different kinds of social ideas and theories. There are old ideas and
theories which have outlived their day and which serve the interests of the
moribund forces of society. Their significance lies in the fact that they
hamper the development, the progress of society. Then there are new and
advanced ideas and theories which serve the interests of the advanced forces of
society. Their significance lies in the fact that they facilitate the
development, the progress of society; and their significance is the greater the
more accurately they reflect the needs of development of the material life of
society.
New
social ideas and theories arise only after the development of the material life
of society has set new tasks before society. But once they have arisen they
become a most potent force which facilitates the carrying out of the new tasks
set by the development of the material life of society, a force which facilitates
the progress of society. It is precisely here that the tremendous organizing,
mobilizing and transforming value of new ideas, new theories, new political
views and new political institutions manifests itself. New social ideas and
theories arise precisely because they are necessary to society, because it is
impossible to carry out the urgent tasks of development of the material life of
society without their organizing, mobilizing and transforming action. Arising
out of the new tasks set by the development of the material life of society,
the new social ideas and theories force their way through, become the
possession of the masses, mobilize and organize them against the moribund
forces of society, and thus facilitate the overthrow of these forces, which
hamper the development of the material life of society.
Thus
social ideas, theories and political institutions, having arisen on the basis
of the urgent tasks of the development of the material life of society, the
development of social being, themselves then react upon social being, upon the
material life of society, creating the conditions necessary for completely
carrying out the urgent tasks of the material life of society, and for
rendering its further development possible.
In
this connection, Marx says:
"Theory
becomes a material force as soon as it has gripped the masses." (Marx and
Engels, Vol. I, p. 406.)
Hence,
in order to be able to influence the conditions of material life of society and
to accelerate their development and their improvement, the party of the
proletariat must rely upon such a social theory, such a social idea as
correctly reflects the needs of development of the material life of society,
and which is therefore capable of setting into motion broad masses of the
people and of mobilizing them and organizing them into a great army of the
proletarian party, prepared to smash the reactionary forces and to clear the
way for the advanced forces of society.
The
fall of the "Economists" and the Mensheviks was due, among other
things, to the fact that they did not recognize the mobilizing, organizing and
transforming role of advanced theory, of advanced ideas and, sinking to vulgar
materialism, reduced the role of these factors almost to nothing, thus
condemning the Party to passivity and inanition.
The
strength and vitality of Marxism-Leninism is derived from the fact that it
relies upon an advanced theory which correctly reflects the needs of
development of the material life of society, that it elevates theory to a
proper level, and that it deems it its duty to utilize every ounce of the
mobilizing, organizing and transforming power of this theory.
That
is the answer historical materialism gives to the question of the relation
between social being and social consciousness, between the conditions of
development of material life and the development of the spiritual life of
society.
3) Historical
Materialism.
It
now remains to elucidate the following question: What, from the viewpoint of
historical materialism, is meant by the "conditions of material life of
society" which in the final analysis determine the physiognomy of society,
its ideas, views, political institutions, etc.?
What,
after all, are these "conditions of material life of society," what
are their distinguishing features?
There
can be no doubt that the concept "conditions of material life of
society" includes, first of all, nature which surrounds society,
geographical environment, which is one of the indispensable and constant
conditions of material life of society and which, of course, influences the
development of society. What role does geographical environment play in the
development of society? Is geographical environment the chief force determining
the physiognomy of society, the character of the social system of man, the transition
from one system to another, or isn't it?
Historical
materialism answers this question in the negative.
Geographical
environment is unquestionably one of the constant and indispensable conditions
of development of society and, of course, influences the development of
society, accelerates or retards its development. But its influence is not the
determining influence, inasmuch as the changes and development of society
proceed at an incomparably faster rate than the changes and development of
geographical environment. in the space of 3000 years three different social
systems have been successively superseded in Europe: the primitive communal
system, the slave system and the feudal system. In the eastern part of Europe,
in the U.S.S.R., even four social systems have been superseded. Yet during this
period geographical conditions in Europe have either not changed at all, or
have changed so slightly that geography takes no note of them. And that is
quite natural. Changes in geographical environment of any importance require
millions of years, whereas a few hundred or a couple of thousand years are
enough for even very important changes in the system of human society.
It
follows from this that geographical environment cannot be the chief cause, the
determining cause of social development; for that which remains almost
unchanged in the course of tens of thousands of years cannot be the chief cause
of development of that which undergoes fundamental changes in the course of a
few hund
Further,
there can be no doubt that the concept "conditions of material life of
society" also includes growth of population, density of population of one
degree or another; for people are an essential element of the conditions of
material life of society, and without a definite minimum number of people there
can be no material life of society. Is growth of population the chief force
that determines the character of the social system of man, or isn't it?
Historical
materialism answers this question too in the negative.
Of
course, growth of population does influence the development of society, does
facilitate or retard the development of society, but it cannot be the chief
force of development of society, and its influence on the development of
society cannot be the determining influence because, by itself, growth of
population does not furnish the clue to the question why a given social system is
replaced precisely by such and such a new system and not by another, why the
primitive communal system is succeeded precisely by the slave system, the slave
system by the feudal system, and the feudal system by the bourgeois system, and
not by some other.
If
growth of population were the determining force of social development, then a
higher density of population would be bound to give rise to a correspondingly
higher type of social system. But we do not find this to be the case. The
density of population in China is four times as great as in the U.S.A., yet the
U.S.A. stands higher than China in the scale of social development; for in
China a semi-feudal system still prevails, whereas the U.S.A. has long ago
reached the highest stage of development of capitalism. The density of
population in Belgium is I9 times as great as in the U.S.A., and 26 times as
great as in the U.S.S.R. Yet the U.S.A. stands higher than Belgium in the scale
of social development; and as for the U.S.S.R., Belgium lags a whole historical
epoch behind this country, for in Belgium the capitalist system prevails,
whereas the U.S.S.R. has already done away with capitalism and has set up a
socialist system.
It
follows from this that growth of population is not, and cannot be, the chief
force of development of society, the force which determines the character of
the social system, the physiognomy of society.
a) What Is the Chief
Determinant Force?
What,
then, is the chief force in the complex of conditions of material life of
society which determines the physiognomy of society, the character of the
social system, the development of society from one system to another?
This
force, historical materialism holds, is the method of procuring the means of
life necessary for human existence, the mode of production of material values –
food, clothing, footwear, houses, fuel, instruments of production, etc. – which
are indispensable for the life and development of society.
In
order to live, people must have food, clothing, footwear, shelter, fuel, etc.; in
order to have these material values, people must produce them; and in order to
produce them, people must have the instruments of production with which food,
clothing, footwear, shelter, fuel, etc., are produced, they must be able to
produce these instruments and to use them.
The
instruments of production wherewith material values are produced, the people
who operate the instruments of production and carry on the production of
material values thanks to a certain production experience and labor skill – all
these elements jointly constitute the productive forces of society.
But
the productive forces are only one aspect of production, only one aspect of the
mode of production, an aspect that expresses the relation of men to the objects
and forces of nature which they make use of for the production of material
values. Another aspect of production, another aspect of the mode of production,
is the relation of men to each other in the process of production, men's
relations of production. Men carry on a struggle against nature and utilize
nature for the production of material values not in isolation from each other,
not as separate individuals, but in common, in groups, in societies.
Production, therefore, is at all times and under all conditions social
production. In the production of material values men enter into mutual
relations of one kind or another within production, into relations of
production of one kind or another. These may be relations of co-operation and
mutual help between people who are free from exploitation; they may be
relations of domination and subordination; and, lastly, they may be
transitional from one form of relations of production to another. But whatever
the character of the relations of production may be, always and in every system
they constitute just as essential an element of production as the productive
forces of society.
"In
production," Marx says, "men not only act on nature but also on one
another. They produce only by co-operating in a certain way and mutually
exchanging their activities. In order to produce, they enter into definite
connections and relations with one another and only within these social
connections and relations does their action on nature, does production, take
place." (Marx and Engels, Vol. V, p. 429.)
Consequently,
production, the mode of production, embraces both the productive forces of
society and men's relations of production, and is thus the embodiment of their
unity in the process of production of material values.
b) The First Feature of
Production
The
first feature of production is that it never stays at one point for a long time
and is always in a state of change and development, and that, furthermore,
changes in the mode of production inevitably call forth changes in the whole
social system, social ideas, political views and political institutions – they
call forth a reconstruction of the whole social and political order. At
different stages of development people make use of different modes of
production, or, to put it more crudely, lead different manners of life. In the
primitive commune there is one mode of production, under slavery there is
another mode of production, under feudalism a third mode of production and so
on. And, correspondingly, men's social system, the spiritual life of men, their
views and political institutions also vary.
Whatever
is the mode of production of a society, such in the main is the society itself,
its ideas and theories, its political views and institutions.
Or,
to put it more crudely, whatever is man's manner of life such is his manner of
thought.
This
means that the history of development of society is above all the history of
the development of production, the history of the modes of production which
succeed each other in the course of centuries, the history of the development
of productive forces and of people's relations of production.
Hence,
the history of social development is at the same time the history of the
producers of material values themselves, the history of the laboring masses,
who are the chief force in the process of production and who carry on the
production of material values necessary for the existence of society.
Hence,
if historical science is to be a real science, it can no longer reduce the
history of social development to the actions of kings and generals, to the
actions of "conquerors" and "subjugators" of states, but
must above all devote itself to the history of the producers of material
values, the history of the laboring masses, the history of peoples.
Hence,
the clue to the study of the laws of history of society must not be sought in
men's minds, in the views and ideas of society, but in the mode of production
practiced by society in any given historical period; it must be sought in the
economic life of society.
Hence,
the prime task of historical science is to study and disclose the laws of
production, the laws of development of the productive forces and of the
relations of production, the laws of economic development of society.
Hence,
if the party of the proletariat is to be a real party, it must above all
acquire a knowledge of the laws of development of production, of the laws of economic
development of society.
Hence,
if it is not to err in policy, the party of the proletariat must both in
drafting its program and in its practical activities proceed primarily from the
laws of development of production from the laws of economic development of
society.
c) The Second Feature of
Production
The
second feature of production is that its changes and development always begin
with changes and development of the productive forces, and in the first place,
with changes and development of the instruments of production. Productive
forces are therefore the most mobile and revolutionary element of productions
First the productive forces of society change and develop, and then, depending
on these changes and in conformity with them, men's relations of production,
their economic relations, change. This, however, does not mean that the
relations of production do not influence the development of the productive
forces and that the latter are not dependent on the former. While their
development is dependent on the development of the productive forces, the
relations of production in their turn react upon the development of the
productive forces, accelerating or retarding it. In this connection it should
be noted that the relations of production cannot for too long a time lag behind
and be in a state of contradiction to the growth of the productive forces,
inasmuch as the productive forces can develop in full measure only when the
relations of production correspond to the character, the state of the
productive forces and allow full scope for their development. Therefore,
however much the relations of production may lag behind the development of the
productive forces, they must, sooner or later, come into correspondence with –
and actually do come into correspondence with – the level of development of the
productive forces, the character of the productive forces. Otherwise we would
have a fundamental violation of the unity of the productive forces and the
relations of production within the system of production, a disruption of
production as a whole, a crisis of production, a destruction of productive
forces.
An
instance in which the relations of production do not correspond to the
character of the productive forces, conflict with them, is the economic crises
in capitalist countries, where private capitalist ownership of the means of
production is in glaring incongruity with the social character of the process
of production, with the character of the productive forces. This results in
economic crises, which lead to the destruction of productive forces.
Furthermore, this incongruity itself constitutes the economic basis of social
revolution, the purpose of which IS to destroy the existing relations of
production and to create new relations of production corresponding to the character
of the productive forces.
In
contrast, an instance in which the relations of production completely
correspond to the character of the productive forces is the socialist national
economy of the U.S.S.R., where the social ownership of the means of production
fully corresponds to the social character of the process of production, and where,
because of this, economic crises and the destruction of productive forces are
unknown.
Consequently,
the productive forces are not only the most mobile and revolutionary element in
production, but are also the determining element in the development of production.
Whatever
are the productive forces such must be the relations of production.
While
the state of the productive forces furnishes the answer to the question – with
what instruments of production do men produce the material values they need? –
the state of the relations of production furnishes the answer to another
question – who owns the means of production (the land, forests, waters, mineral
resources, raw materials, instruments of production, production premises, means
of transportation and communication, etc.), who commands the means of
production, whether the whole of society, or individual persons, groups, or
classes which utilize them for the exploitation of other persons, groups or
classes?
Here
is a rough picture of the development of productive forces from ancient times
to our day. The transition from crude stone tools to the bow and arrow, and the
accompanying transition from the life of hunters to the domestication of
animals and primitive pasturage; the transition from stone tools to metal tools
(the iron axe, the wooden plow fitted with an iron coulter, etc.), with a
corresponding transition to tillage and agriculture; a further improvement in
metal tools for the working up of materials, the introduction of the
blacksmith's bellows, the introduction of pottery, with a corresponding
development of handicrafts, the separation of handicrafts from agriculture, the
development of an independent handicraft industry and, subsequently, of
manufacture; the transition from handicraft tools to machines and the
transformation of handicraft and manufacture into machine industry; the
transition to the machine system and the rise of modern large-scale machine
industry – such is a general and far from complete picture of the development
of the productive forces of society in the course of man's history. It will be
clear that the development and improvement of the instruments of production was
effected by men who were related to production, and not independently of men;
and, consequently, the change and development of the instruments of production
was accompanied by a change and development of men, as the most important
element of the productive forces, by a change and development of their
production experience, their In conformity with the change and development of
the productive forces of society in the course of history, men's relations of
production, their economic relations also changed and developed.
Main
types of Relations of Production
Five
main types of relations of production are known to history: primitive communal,
slave, feudal, capitalist and socialist.
The
basis of the relations of production under the primitive communal system is
that the means of production are socially owned. This in the main corresponds
to the character of the productive forces of that period. Stone tools, and,
later, the bow and arrow, precluded the possibility of men individually
combating the forces of nature and beasts of prey. In order to gather the
fruits of the forest, to catch fish, to build some sort of habitation, men were
obliged to work in common if they did not want to die of starvation, or fall
victim to beasts of prey or to neighboring societies. Labor in common led to
the common ownership of the means of production, as well as of the fruits of
production. Here the conception of private ownership of the means of production
did not yet exist, except for the personal ownership of certain implements of
production which were at the same time means of defense against beasts of prey.
Here there was no exploitation, no classes.
The
basis of the relations of production under the slave system is that the
slave-owner owns the means of production, he also owns the worker in production
– the slave, whom he can sell, purchase, or kill as though he were an animal.
Such relations of production in the main correspond to the state of the
productive forces of that period. Instead of stone tools, men now have metal
tools at their command; instead of the wretched and primitive husbandry of the
hunter, who knew neither pasturage nor tillage, there now appear pasturage
tillage, handicrafts, and a division of labor between these branches of
production. There appears the possibility of the exchange of products between
individuals and between societies, of the accumulation of wealth in the hands
of a few, the actual accumulation of the means of production in the hands of a
minority, and the possibility of subjugation of the majority by a minority and
the conversion of the majority into slaves. Here we no longer find the common
and free labor of all members of society in the production process – here there
prevails the forced labor of slaves, who are exploited by the non-laboring
slave-owners. Here, therefore, there is no common ownership of the means of
production or of the fruits of production. It is replaced by private ownership.
Here the slaveowner appears as the prime and principal property owner in the
full sense of the term.
Rich
and poor, exploiters and exploited, people with full rights and people with no
rights, and a fierce class struggle between them – such is the picture of the
slave system.
The
basis of the relations of production under the feudal system is that the feudal
lord owns the means of production and does not fully own the worker in
production – the serf, whom the feudal lord can no longer kill, but whom he can
buy and sell. Alongside of feudal ownership there exists individual ownership
by the peasant and the handicraftsman of his implements of production and his
private enterprise based on his personal labor. Such relations of production in
the main correspond to the state of the productive forces of that period.
Further improvements in the smelting and working of iron; the spread of the
iron plow and the loom; the further development of agriculture, horticulture,
viniculture and dairying; the appearance of manufactories alongside of the
handicraft workshops – such are the characteristic features of the state of the
productive forces.
The
new productive forces demand that the laborer shall display some kind of
initiative in production and an inclination for work, an interest in work. The
feudal lord therefore discards the slave, as a laborer who has no interest in
work and is entirely without initiative, and prefers to deal with the serf, who
has his own husbandry, implements of production, and a certain interest in work
essential for the cultivation of the land and for the payment in kind of a part
of his harvest to the feudal lord.
Here
private ownership is further developed. Exploitation is nearly as severe as it
was under slavery – it is only slightly mitigated. A class struggle between
exploiters and exploited is the principal feature of the feudal system.
The
basis of the relations of production under the capitalist system is that the
capitalist owns the means of production, but not the workers in production –
the wage laborers, whom the capitalist can neither kill nor sell because they
are personally free, but who are deprived of means of production and) in order
not to die of hunger, are obliged to sell their labor power to the capitalist
and to bear the yoke of exploitation. Alongside of capitalist property in the
means of production, we find, at first on a wide scale, private property of the
peasants and handicraftsmen in the means of production, these peasants and handicraftsmen
no longer being serfs, and their private property being based on personal
labor. In place of the handicraft workshops and manufactories there appear huge
mills and factories equipped with machinery. In place of the manorial estates
tilled by the primitive implements of production of the peasant, there now
appear large capitalist farms run on scientific lines and supplied with
agricultural machinery
The
new productive forces require that the workers in production shall be better
educated and more intelligent than the downtrodden and ignorant serfs, that
they be able to understand machinery and operate it properly. Therefore, the
capitalists prefer to deal with wage-workers, who are free from the bonds of
serfdom and who are educated enough to be able properly to operate machinery.
But
having developed productive forces to a tremendous extent, capitalism has
become enmeshed in contradictions which it is unable to solve. By producing
larger and larger quantities of commodities, and reducing their prices,
capitalism intensifies competition, ruins the mass of small and medium private
owners, converts them into proletarians and reduces their purchasing power,
with the result that it becomes impossible to dispose of the commodities
produced. On the other hand, by expanding production and concentrating millions
of workers in huge mills and factories, capitalism lends the process of
production a social character and thus undermines its own foundation, inasmuch
as the social character of the process of production demands the social
ownership of the means of production; yet the means of production remain
private capitalist property, which is incompatible with the social character of
the process of production.
These
irreconcilable contradictions between the character of the productive forces
and the relations of production make themselves felt in periodical crises of
over-production, when the capitalists, finding no effective demand for their
goods owing to the ruin of the mass of the population which they themselves
have brought about, are compelled to burn products, destroy manufactured goods,
suspend production, and destroy productive forces at a time when millions of
people are forced to suffer unemployment and starvation, not because there are
not enough goods, but because there is an overproduction of goods.
This
means that the capitalist relations of production have ceased to correspond to
the state of productive forces of society and have come into irreconcilable
contradiction with them.
This
means that capitalism is pregnant with revolution, whose mission it is to
replace the existing capitalist ownership of the means of production by
socialist ownership.
This
means that the main feature of the capitalist system is a most acute class
struggle between the exploiters and the exploited.
The
basis of the relations of production under the socialist system, which so far
has been established only in the U.S.S.R., is the social ownership of the means
of production. Here there are no longer exploiters and exploited. The goods
produced are distributed according to labor performed, on the principle:
"He who does not work, neither shall he eat." Here the mutual
relations of people in the process of production are marked by comradely
cooperation and the socialist mutual assistance of workers who are free from
exploitation. Here the relations of production fully correspond to the state of
productive forces; for the social character of the process of production is
reinforced by the social ownership of the means of production.
For
this reason socialist production in the U.S.S.R. knows no periodical crises of
over-production and their accompanying absurdities.
For
this reason, the productive forces here develop at an accelerated pace; for the
relations of production that correspond to them offer full scope for such
development.
Such
is the picture of the development of men's relations of production in the
course of human history.
Such
is the dependence of the development of the relations of production on the
development of the productive forces of society, and primarily, on the
development of the instruments of production, the dependence by virtue of which
the changes and development of the productive forces sooner or later lead to
corresponding changes and development of the relations of production.
"The
use and fabrication of instruments of labor," says Marx, "although
existing in the germ among certain species of animals, is specifically
characteristic of the human labor-process, and Franklin therefore defines man
as a tool-making animal. Relics of bygone instruments of labor possess the same
importance for the investigation of extinct economical forms of society, as do
fossil bones for the determination of extinct species of animals. It is not the
articles made, but how they are made that enables us to distinguish different
economical epochs. Instruments of labor not only supply a standard of the
degree of development to which human labor has attained, but they are also
indicators of the social conditions under which that labor is carried on."
(Marx, Capital, Vol. I, 1935, p. 121.)
And
further:
–
"Social relations are closely bound up with productive forces. In
acquiring new productive forces men change their mode of production; and in
changing their mode of production, in changing the way of earning their living,
they change all their social relations. The hand-mill gives you society with
the feudal lord; the steam-mill, society with the industrial capitalist."
(Marx and Engels, Vol. V, p. 564.)
–
"There is a continual movement of growth in productive forces, of
destruction in social relations, of formation in ideas; the only immutable
thing is the abstraction of movement." (Ibid., p. 364.)
Speaking
of historical materialism as formulated in The Communist Manifesto, Engels
says:
"Economic
production and the structure of society of every historical epoch necessarily
arising therefrom constitute the foundation for the political and intellectual
history of that epoch; ... consequently (ever since the dissolution of the primeval
communal ownership of land) all history has been a history of class struggles,
of struggles between exploited and exploiting, between dominated and dominating
classes at various stages of social development; ... this struggle, however,
has now reached a stage where the exploited and oppressed class (the
proletariat) can no longer emancipate itself from the class which exploits and
oppresses it (the bourgeoisie), without at the same time for ever freeing the
whole of society from exploitation, oppression and class struggles...."
(Engels' Preface to the German Edition of the Manifesto.)
d)
The Third Feature of Production
The
third feature of production is that the rise of new productive forces and of
the relations of production corresponding to them does not take place
separately from the old system, after the disappearance of the old system, but
within the old system; it takes place not as a result of the deliberate and
conscious activity of man, but spontaneously, unconsciously, independently of
the will of man It takes place spontaneously and independently of the will of
man for two reasons.
Firstly,
because men are not free to choose one mode of production or another, because
as every new generation enters life it finds productive forces and relations of
production already existing as the result of the work of former generations,
owing to which it is obliged at first to accept and adapt itself to everything
it finds ready-made in the sphere of production in order to be able to produce
material values.
Secondly,
because, when improving one instrument of production or another, one clement of
the productive forces or another, men do not realize, do not understand or stop
to reflect what social results these improvements will lead to, but only think
of their everyday interests, of lightening their labor and of securing some
direct and tangible advantage for themselves.
When,
gradually and gropingly, certain members of primitive communal society passed
from the use of stone tools to the use of iron tools, they, of course, did not
know and did not stop to reflect what social results this innovation would lead
to; they did not understand or realize that the change to metal tools meant a
revolution in production, that it would in the long run lead to the slave system.
They simply wanted to lighten their labor and secure an immediate and tangible
advantage; their conscious activity was confined within the narrow bounds of
this everyday personal interest.
When,
in the period of the feudal system, the young bourgeoisie of Europe began to
erect, alongside of the small guild workshops, large manufactories, and thus
advanced the productive forces of society, it, of course, did not know and did
not stop to reflect what social consequences this innovation would lead to; it
did not realize or understand that this "small" innovation would lead
to a regrouping of social forces which was to end in a revolution both against
the power of kings, whose favors it so highly valued, and against the nobility,
to whose ranks its foremost representatives not infrequently aspired. It simply
wanted to lower the cost of producing goods, to throw larger quantities of
goods on the markets of Asia and of recently discovered America, and to make
bigger profits. Its conscious activity was confined within the narrow bounds of
this commonplace practical aim.
When
the Russian capitalists, in conjunction with foreign capitalists, energetically
implanted modern large-scale machine industry in Russia, while leaving tsardom
intact and turning the peasants over to the tender mercies of the landlords,
they, of course, did not know and did not stop to reflect what social
consequences this extensive growth of productive forces would lead to; they did
not realize or understand that this big leap in the realm of the productive
forces of society would lead to a regrouping of social forces that would enable
the proletariat to effect a union with the peasantry and to bring about a
victorious socialist revolution. They simply wanted to expand industrial production
to the limit, to gain control of the huge home market, to become monopolists,
and to squeeze as much profit as possible out of the national economy.
Their
conscious activity did not extend beyond their commonplace, strictly practical
interests.
Accordingly,
Marx says:
"In
the social production of their life (that is. in the production of the material
values necessary to the life of men – J. St.), men enter into definite
relations that are indispensable and independent of their will, relations of
production which correspond to a definite stage of development of their
material productive forces." (Marx, Selected Works, Vol. I, p 269).
This,
however, does not mean that changes in the relations of production, and the
transition from old relations of production to new relations of production
proceed smoothly, without conflicts, without upheavals. On the contrary such a
transition usually takes place by means of the revolutionary overthrow of the
old relations of production and the establishment of new relations of
production. Up to a certain period the development of the productive forces and
the changes in the realm of the relations of production proceed spontaneously
independently of the will of men. But that is so only up to a certain moment,
until the new and developing productive forces have reached a proper state of
maturity After the new productive forces have matured, the existing relations
of production and their upholders – the ruling classes – become that
"insuperable" obstacle which can only be removed by the conscious
action of the new classes, by the forcible acts of these classes, by
revolution. Here there stands out in bold relief the tremendous role of new
social ideas, of new political institutions, of a new political power, whose
mission it is to abolish by force the old relations of production. Out of the
conflict between the new productive forces and the old relations of production,
out of the new economic demands of society, there arise new social ideas; the
new ideas organize and mobilize the masses; the masses become welded into a new
political army, create a new revolutionary power, and make use of it to abolish
by force the old system of relations of production, and to firmly establish the
new system. The spontaneous process of development yields place to the
conscious actions of men, peaceful development to violent upheaval, evolution
to revolution.
"The
proletariat," says Marx, "during its contest with the bourgeoisie is
compelled, by the force of circumstances, to organize itself as a class...by
means of a revolution, it makes itself the ruling class, and, as such, sweeps
away by force the old conditions of production...." (Manifesto of the
Communist Party, 1938, p. 52.)
And
further:
–
"The proletariat will use its political supremacy to wrest, by degrees,
all capital from the bourgeoisie, to centralize all instruments of production
in the hands of the State, i.e., of the proletariat organized as the ruling
class; and to increase the total of productive forces as rapidly as possible."
(Ibid., p. 50 )
–
"Force is the midwife of every old society pregnant with a new one."
(Marx, Capital, Vol. I, 1955, p. 603.)
Here
is the formulation – a formulation of genius – of the essence of historical
materialism given by Marx in 1859 in his historic Preface to his famous book, A
Contribution to the Critique of Political Economy:
"In
the social production of their life, men enter into definite relations that are
indispensable and independent of their will, relations of production which correspond
to a definite stage of development of their material productive forces. The sum
total of these relations of production constitutes the economic structure of
society, the real foundation, on which rises a legal and political
superstructure and to which correspond definite forms of social consciousness.
The mode of production of material life conditions the social, political and
intellectual life process in general. It is not the consciousness of men that
determines their being, but, on the contrary, their social being that
determines their consciousness. At a certain stage of their development, the
material productive forces of society come in conflict with the existing
relations of production, or – what is but a legal expression for the same thing
– with the property relations within which they have been at work hitherto.
From forms of development of the productive forces these relations turn into
their fetters. Then begins an epoch of social revolution. With the change of
the economic foundation the entire immense superstructure is more or less
rapidly transformed. In considering such transformations a distinction should
always be made between the material transformation of the economic conditions
of production, which can be determined with the precision of natural science,
and the legal, political, religious, aesthetic or philosophic – in short,
ideological forms in which men become conscious of this conflict and fight it
out. Just as our opinion of an individual is not based on what he thinks of himself,
so can we not judge of such a period of transformation by its own
consciousness; on the contrary this consciousness must be explained rather from
the contradictions of material life, from the existing conflict between the
social productive forces and the relations of production. No social order ever
perishes before all the productive forces for which there is room in it have
developed; and new, higher relations of production never appear before the
material conditions of their existence have matured in the womb of the old
society itself. Therefore mankind always sets itself only such tasks as it can
solve; since looking at the matter more closely, it will always be found that
the task itself arises only when the material conditions for its solution already
exist or are at least in the process of formation." (Marx, Selected Works,
Vol. I, pp. 269-70.)
Such
is Marxist materialism as applied to social life, to the history of society.
Such
are the principal features of dialectical and historical materialism.
No comments:
Post a Comment